➊ Classical cartography, formally
Hierarchies of syntactic categories, each given rise to by a binary relation \(\mathbf{R}_\mathcal{A}\) on categories of a major part of speech \(\mathcal{A}\), such that \(\forall X, Y, Z \in \mathcal{A}\)
- \(\neg\mathbf{R}_\mathcal{A}(X, X)\) (irreflexivity)
- \(\mathbf{R}_\mathcal{A}(X, Y) \Rightarrow \neg\mathbf{R}_\mathcal{A}(Y, X)\) (asymmetry)
- \(\mathbf{R}_\mathcal{A}(X, Y) \wedge \mathbf{R}_\mathcal{A}(Y, Z) \) \(\Rightarrow \mathbf{R}_\mathcal{A}(X, Z)\) (transitivity)
- \(\forall X, Y \in \mathcal{A}, \mathbf{R}_\mathcal{A}(X, Y) \vee \) \(\mathbf{R}_\mathcal{A}(Y, X)\) (totality)
Thus, a classical cartographic hierarchy is a strict total order. The binary relation in question is usually deemed one of selection:
- \(\mathbf{R}_\mathcal{A}(X, Y)\) iff \(X\) selects \(Y\)
The classical view is multiply problematic.
➋ Problems of classical cartography
1. Transitivity failure
- Norwegian (Nilsen 2003)
\(\mathbf{R}_\mathcal{V}(\mathbf{H}(\text{possibly}), \text{Neg})\; \wedge\)
\(\mathbf{R}_\mathcal{V}(\text{Neg}, \mathbf{H}(\text{always}))\; \wedge\)
\(\mathbf{R}_\mathcal{V}(\mathbf{H}(\text{possibly}), \mathbf{H}(\text{always}))\; \wedge\)
\(\mathbf{R}_\mathcal{V}(\mathbf{H}(\text{always}), \mathbf{H}(\text{possibly}))\)
[\(\mathbf{H}(e)\) := head of projection for expression \(e\)] - Venetian (van Craenenbroeck 2006)
\(\mathbf{R}_\mathcal{V}(\text{Topic}, \text{Focus})\; \wedge\)
\(\mathbf{R}_\mathcal{V}(\text{Focus}, \text{C})\; \wedge\)
\(\mathbf{R}_\mathcal{V}(\text{C}, \text{Topic})\) - Imbabura Quechua (Bruening 2019)
\(\mathbf{R}_\mathcal{V}(1\text{sg}, \text{Prog})\; \wedge\)
\(\mathbf{R}_\mathcal{V}(\text{Mod}_\text{des}, 1\text{sg})\; \wedge\)
\(\mathbf{R}_\mathcal{V}(\text{Prog}, \text{Mod}_\text{des})\; \wedge\)
\(\mathbf{R}_\mathcal{V}(\text{Mod}_\text{des}, \text{Prog})\)
One could argue away some or even all of the above cases by derivational means (e.g., movement, Zwart 2009), but the problem of transitivity is more than counterexamples:
- Selection is not a transitive relation.
- Larson's (2021) “problem of plenitude”
Either transitivity or the selection-based definition of \(\mathbf{R}\) is wrong.
2. Totality failure
Previous concerns about the foundation of cartography mostly target transitivity, but Song (2019) further notices that the totality condition on \(\mathbf{R}\) is also problematic.
Some categories belong to the same hierarchy but do not co-occur by design.
- “Flavored” categories like Chomsky’s \(v\)/\(v^*\) and Lowenstamm’s (2008) gendered \(n\)s
- Other complementary categories like Chomsky’s T/Tdef
However \(\mathbf{R}\) is defined, it should have room for incomparable elements:
- \(\exists X, Y \in \mathcal{A}, \neg\mathbf{R}_\mathcal{A}(X, Y) \wedge \)\(\neg\mathbf{R}_\mathcal{A}(Y, X)\)
➌ Saving by weakening
Two previous attempts to “save” cartography by weakening its order relation:
1. Song (2019): partial order
reflexive, transitive, antisymmetric
- Allowing for incomparable categories
- A unified defining criterion for all \(\mathbf{R}\)s
(based on but crucially isn't selection) - Each \(\mathbf{R}\) defined for an entire hierarchy
- Key: derivation vs. ontology
2. Larson (2021): total preorder
reflexive, transitive, total
- Allowing for cycles
- No unified defining criterion for \(\mathbf{R}\)s
(also not selection, partly ontological) - Each \(\mathbf{R}\) only defined for a local zone
- Key: category ordering ➔ feature ordering
The different ways of weakening are due to the authors' different empirical foci (totality vs. transitivity failure). Larson reshapes the classical view more substantially, while Song merely adjusts its individual components.
Shared merit: freed from “selection pitfall”
transitivity reflexivity
➍ A middle-way proposal
All functional hierarchies are preorders. Some of them are furthermore total preorders, partial orders, or linear orders.
R = reflexive, Tr = transitive, To = total, Ant = antisymmetric
\(\forall X, Y \in \mathcal{A},\) if \(Y\) functionally selects \(X\) in derivation, then \(X\) can fall in the scope of \(Y\) in the background ontology, written \(X \sqsubseteq Y\). The latter criterion defines functional hierarchies.
➎ Possible functional hierarchies
Notation: \(X \rightarrow Y \equiv X \sqsubseteq Y,\) \(\{X, Y\} \equiv \) \(X\) and \(Y\) are incomparable.
The chain (linear order):
\[\dots X \rightarrow Y \rightarrow Z \rightarrow W \rightarrow V\dots\]The connected digraph, with incomparable elements (preorder):
\[\dots X \rightarrow Y \leftrightarrows Z \rightarrow \{W_1, W_2\} \rightarrow V\dots\]The connected digraph, w/o incomparable elements (total preorder):
\[\dots X \rightarrow Y \leftrightarrows Z \rightarrow W \leftrightarrows V\dots\]The DAG (partial order):
\[\dots X \rightarrow \{Y_1, Y_2, Y_3\} \rightarrow Z \rightarrow \{W_1, W_2\} \rightarrow V\dots\]➏ Bigger picture
The middle-way proposal can be extended from individual hierarchies to the entire functional category inventory. Consider two hierarchies defined by \(\mathbf{R}_\mathcal{A}\) and \(\mathbf{R}_\mathcal{B}\):
\[\mathcal{A}: \dots X \rightarrow \{Y_1, Y_2\} \rightarrow Z \rightarrow W\dots\] \[\mathcal{B}: \dots X \leftrightarrows Y \rightarrow Z \rightarrow W\dots \]The two combined is still a preorder and may be viewed as a “superhierarchy.” One may also study the formal relations (e.g., monotone functions) across such hierarchies. Song (2019) explores such metatheoretical issues with the aid of mathematical category theory.
➐ Remaining issues
For future research:
- The weakest hierarchy in ➎ is actually not a fully general preorder but a directed one. So, Definition 1 may need adjustment.
- If it turns out that all cases of transitivity failure can be argued away derivationally, then no cycles occur, and we end up with just partial orders (as in Song 2019).
- If so, we can further explore the specific shape of directedness in ➎ and potentially give cartographic hierarchies an upgraded, lattice-theoretic foundation.